Symmetric groups
Theorem 1: Let
be any set. Then, the set
of bijections from
to itself,
, form a group under composition of functions.
Proof: We have to verify the group axioms. Associativity is fulfilled since composition of functions is always associative:
where the composition is defined. The identity element is the identity function given by
for all
. Finally, the inverse of a function
is the function
taking
to
for all
. This function exists and is unique since
is a bijection. Thus
is a group, as stated. ∎
is called the symmetric group on
. When
, we write its symmetric group as
, and we call this group the symmetric group on
letters. It is also called the group of permutations on
letters. As we will see shortly, this is an appropriate name.
Instead of
, we will use a different symbol, namely
, for the identity function in
.
When
, we can specify
by specifying where it sends each element. There are many ways to encode this information mathematically. One obvious way is to identify
as the unique
matrix with value
in the entries
and
elsewhere. Composition of functions then corresponds to multiplication of matrices. Indeed, the matrix corresponding to
has value
in the entries
, which is the same as
, so the product has value
in the entries
. This notation may seem cumbersome. Luckily, there exists a more convenient notation, which we will make use of.
We can represent any
by a
matrix
. We obviously lose the correspondence between function composition and matrix multiplication, but we gain a more readable notation. For the time being, we will use this.
Remark 2: Let
. Then the product
is the function obtained by first acting with
, and then by
. That is,
. This point is important to keep in mind when computing products in
. Some textbooks try to remedy the frequent confusion by writing functions like
, that is, writing arguments on the left of functions. We will not do this, as it is not standard. The reader should use the next example and theorem to get a feeling for products in
.
Example 3: We will show the multiplication table for
. We introduce the special notation for
:
,
,
,
,
and
. The multiplication table for
is then

Theorem 4:
has order
.
Proof: This follows from a counting argument. We can specify a unique element in
by specifying where each
is sent. Also, any permutation can be specified this way. Let
. In choosing
we are completely free and have
choices. Then, when choosing
we must choose from
, giving a total of
choices. Continuing in this fashion, we see that for
we must choose from
, giving a total of
choices. The total number of ways in which we can specify an element, and thus the number of elements in
is then
, as was to be shown. ∎
Theorem 5:
is non-abelian for all
.
Proof: Let
be the function only interchanging 1 and 2, and
be the function only interchanging 2 and 3. Then
and
. Since
,
is not abelian. ∎
Definition 6: Let
such that
for some
. Then
is called an
-cycle, where
is the smallest positive such integer. Let
be the set of integers
such that
. Two cycles
are called disjoint if
. Also, a 2-cycle is called a transposition.
Remark 3: It's important to realize that if
, then so is
. If
, then if
we have that
is not 1–1.
Theorem 7: Let
. If
, then
.
Proof: For any integer
such that
but
we have
. A similar argument holds for
but
. If
, we must have
. Since
, we have now exhausted every
, and we are done. ∎
Theorem 8: Any permutation can be represented as a composition of disjoint cycles.
Proof: Let
. Choose an element
and compute
. Since
is finite of order
, we know that
exists and
. We have now found a
-cycle
including
. Since
, this cycle may be factored out from
to obtain
. Repeat this process, which terminates since
is finite, and we have constructed a composition of disjoint cycles that equals
. ∎
Now that we have shown that all permuations are just compositions of disjoint cycles, we can introduce the ultimate shorthand notation for permutations. For an
-cycle
, we can show its action by choosing any element
and writing
.
Theorem 9: Any
-cycle can be represented as a composition of transpositions.
Proof: Let
. Then,
(check this!), omitting the composition sign
. Interate this process to obtain
. ∎
Note 10: This way of representing
as a product of transpositions is not unique. However, as we will see now, the "parity" of such a representation is well defined.
Definition 11: The parity of a permutation is even if it can be expressed as a product of an even number of transpositions. Otherwise, it is odd. We define the function
if
is even and
if
is odd.
Lemma 12: The identity
has even parity.
Proof: Observe first that
for
. Thus the minimum number of transpositions necessary to represent
is 2:
. Now, assume that for any representation using less than
transpositions must be even. Thus, let
. Now, since in particular
, we must have
for some
. Since disjoint transpositions commute, and
where
, it is always possible to configure the transpositions such that the first two transpositions are either
, reducing the number of transposition by two, or
. In this case we have reduced the number of transpositions involving
by 1. We restart the same process as above. with the new representation. Since only a finite number of transpositions move
, we will eventually be able to cancel two permutations and be left with
transpositions in the product. Then, by the induction hypothesis,
must be even and so
is even as well, proving the lemma. ∎
Theorem 13: The parity of a permutation, and thus the
function, is well-defined.
Proof: Let
and write
as a product of transposition in two different ways:
. Then, since
has even parity by Lemma 11 and
. Thus,
, and
, so
has a uniquely defined parity, and consequentially
is well-defined. ∎
Theorem 14: Let
. Then,
.
Proof: Decompose
and
into transpositions:
,
. Then
has parity given by
. If both are even or odd,
is even and indeed
. If one is odd and one is even,
is odd and again
, proving the theorem. ∎
Lemma 15: The number of even permutations in
equals the number of odd permutations.
Proof: Let
be any even permutation and
a transposition. Then
has odd parity by Theorem 14. Let
be the set of even permutations and
the set of odd permutations. Then the function
given by
for any
and a fixed transposition
, is a bijection. (Indeed, it is a transposition in
!) Thus
and
have the same number of elements, as stated. ∎
Definition 16: Let the set of all even permutations in
be denoted by
.
is called the alternating group on
letters.
Theorem 17:
is a group, and is a subgroup of
of order
.
Proof: We first show that
is a group under composition. Then it is automatically a subgroup of
. That
is closed under composition follows from Theorem 14 and associativity is inherited from
. Also, the identity permutation is even, so
. Thus
is a group and a subgroup of
. Since the number of even and odd permutations are equal by Lemma 14, we then have that
, proving the theorem. ∎
Theorem 18: Let
. Then
is generated by the 3-cycles in
.
Proof: We must show that any even permutation can be decomposed into 3-cycles. It is sufficient to show that this is the case for pairs of transpositions. Let
be distinct. Then, by some casework,
- i)
,
- ii)
, and
- iii)
,
proving the theorem. ∎
In a previous section we proved Lagrange's Theorem: The order of any subgroup divides the order of the parent group. However, the converse statement, that a group has a subgroup for every divisor of its order, is false! The smallest group providing a counterexample is the alternating group
, which has order 12 but no subgroup of order 6. It has subgroups of orders 3 and 4, corresponding respectively to the cyclic group of order 3 and the Klein 4-group. However, if we add any other element to the subgroup corresponding to
, it generates the whole group
. We leave it to the reader to show this.